Contents
Proof that π is irrational
In the 1760s, Johann Heinrich Lambert was the first to prove that the number π is irrational, meaning it cannot be expressed as a fraction a/b, where a and b are both integers. In the 19th century, Charles Hermite found a proof that requires no prerequisite knowledge beyond basic calculus. Three simplifications of Hermite's proof are due to Mary Cartwright, Ivan Niven, and Nicolas Bourbaki. Another proof, which is a simplification of Lambert's proof, is due to Miklós Laczkovich. Many of these are proofs by contradiction. In 1882, Ferdinand von Lindemann proved that \pi is not just irrational, but transcendental as well.
Lambert's proof
In 1761, Johann Heinrich Lambert proved that \pi is irrational by first showing that this continued fraction expansion holds: Then Lambert proved that if x is non-zero and rational, then this expression must be irrational. Since, it follows that \tfrac\pi4 is irrational, and thus \pi is also irrational. A simplification of Lambert's proof is given below.
Hermite's proof
Written in 1873, this proof uses the characterization of \pi as the smallest positive number whose half is a zero of the cosine function and it actually proves that \pi^2 is irrational. As in many proofs of irrationality, it is a proof by contradiction. Consider the sequences of real functions A_n and U_n for n \in \N_0 defined by: Using induction we can prove that and therefore we have: So which is equivalent to Using the definition of the sequence and employing induction we can show that where P_n and Q_n are polynomial functions with integer coefficients and the degree of P_n is smaller than or equal to In particular, Hermite also gave a closed expression for the function A_n, namely He did not justify this assertion, but it can be proved easily. First of all, this assertion is equivalent to Proceeding by induction, take n = 0. and, for the inductive step, consider any natural number n. If then, using integration by parts and Leibniz's rule, one gets If with p and q in \N, then, since the coefficients of P_n are integers and its degree is smaller than or equal to is some integer N. In other words, But this number is clearly greater than 0. On the other hand, the limit of this quantity as n goes to infinity is zero, and so, if n is large enough, N < 1. Thereby, a contradiction is reached. Hermite did not present his proof as an end in itself but as an afterthought within his search for a proof of the transcendence of \pi. He discussed the recurrence relations to motivate and to obtain a convenient integral representation. Once this integral representation is obtained, there are various ways to present a succinct and self-contained proof starting from the integral (as in Cartwright's, Bourbaki's or Niven's presentations), which Hermite could easily see (as he did in his proof of the transcendence of e ). Moreover, Hermite's proof is closer to Lambert's proof than it seems. In fact, A_n(x) is the "residue" (or "remainder") of Lambert's continued fraction for \tan x.
Cartwright's proof
Harold Jeffreys wrote that this proof was set as an example in an exam at Cambridge University in 1945 by Mary Cartwright, but that she had not traced its origin. It still remains on the 4th problem sheet today for the Analysis IA course at Cambridge University. Consider the integrals where n is a non-negative integer. Two integrations by parts give the recurrence relation If then this becomes Furthermore, and Hence for all n \in \Z_+, where P_n(x) and Q_n(x) are polynomials of degree \leq n, and with integer coefficients (depending on n). Take and suppose if possible that where a and b are natural numbers (i.e., assume that \pi is rational). Then The right side is an integer. But since the interval [-1,1] has length 2 and the function being integrated takes only values between 0 and 1. On the other hand, Hence, for sufficiently large n that is, we could find an integer between 0 and 1. That is the contradiction that follows from the assumption that \pi is rational. This proof is similar to Hermite's proof. Indeed, However, it is clearly simpler. This is achieved by omitting the inductive definition of the functions A_n and taking as a starting point their expression as an integral.
Niven's proof
This proof uses the characterization of \pi as the smallest positive zero of the sine function. Suppose that \pi is rational, i.e. \pi = a/b for some integers a and b which may be taken without loss of generality to both be positive. Given any positive integer n, we define the polynomial function: and, for each x \in \R let Claim 1: is an integer. Proof: Expanding f as a sum of monomials, the coefficient of x^k is a number of the form c_k /n! where c_k is an integer, which is 0 if k < n. Therefore, f^{(k)}(0) is 0 when k < n and it is equal to if ; in each case, f^{(k)}(0) is an integer and therefore F(0) is an integer. On the other hand, and so for each non-negative integer k. In particular, Therefore, is also an integer and so F(\pi) is an integer (in fact, it is easy to see that ). Since F(0) and F(\pi) are integers, so is their sum. Claim 2: Proof: Since is the zero polynomial, we have The derivatives of the sine and cosine function are given by sin' = cos and cos' = −sin. Hence the product rule implies By the fundamental theorem of calculus Since and (here we use the above-mentioned characterization of \pi as a zero of the sine function), Claim 2 follows. Conclusion: Since f(x) > 0 and \sin x > 0 for 0 < x < \pi (because \pi is the smallest positive zero of the sine function), Claims 1 and 2 show that is a positive integer. Since and for we have, by the original definition of f, which is smaller than 1 for large n, hence for these n, by Claim 2. This is impossible for the positive integer This shows that the original assumption that \pi is rational leads to a contradiction, which concludes the proof. The above proof is a polished version, which is kept as simple as possible concerning the prerequisites, of an analysis of the formula which is obtained by 2n + 2 integrations by parts. Claim 2 essentially establishes this formula, where the use of F hides the iterated integration by parts. The last integral vanishes because f^{(2n+2)} is the zero polynomial. Claim 1 shows that the remaining sum is an integer. Niven's proof is closer to Cartwright's (and therefore Hermite's) proof than it appears at first sight. In fact, Therefore, the substitution xz = y turns this integral into In particular, Another connection between the proofs lies in the fact that Hermite already mentions that if f is a polynomial function and then from which it follows that
Bourbaki's proof
Bourbaki's proof is outlined as an exercise in his calculus treatise. For each natural number b and each non-negative integer n, define Since A_n(b) is the integral of a function defined on [0,\pi] that takes the value 0 at 0 and \pi and which is greater than 0 otherwise, A_n(b) > 0. Besides, for each natural number b, A_n(b) < 1 if n is large enough, because and therefore On the other hand, repeated integration by parts allows us to deduce that, if a and b are natural numbers such that \pi = a/b and f is the polynomial function from [0, \pi] into \R defined by then: This last integral is 0, since f^{(2n+1)} is the null function (because f is a polynomial function of degree 2n). Since each function f^{(k)} (with ) takes integer values at 0 and \pi and since the same thing happens with the sine and the cosine functions, this proves that A_n(b) is an integer. Since it is also greater than 0, it must be a natural number. But it was also proved that A_n(b) < 1 if n is large enough, thereby reaching a contradiction. This proof is quite close to Niven's proof, the main difference between them being the way of proving that the numbers A_n(b) are integers.
Laczkovich's proof
Miklós Laczkovich's proof is a simplification of Lambert's original proof. He considers the functions These functions are clearly defined for any real number x. Besides Claim 1: The following recurrence relation holds for any real number x: Proof: This can be proved by comparing the coefficients of the powers of x. Claim 2: For each real number x, Proof: In fact, the sequence x^{2n}/n! is bounded (since it converges to 0) and if C is an upper bound and if k > 1, then Claim 3: If x \neq 0, x^2 is rational, and then Proof: Otherwise, there would be a number y \neq 0 and integers a and b such that f_k(x) = ay and To see why, take a = 0, and b = 1 if otherwise, choose integers a and b such that and define In each case, y cannot be 0, because otherwise it would follow from claim 1 that each f_{k+n}(x) (n \in \N) would be 0, which would contradict claim 2. Now, take a natural number c such that all three numbers bc/k, ck/x^2, and c/x^2 are integers and consider the sequence Then On the other hand, it follows from claim 1 that which is a linear combination of g_{n+1} and g_n with integer coefficients. Therefore, each g_n is an integer multiple of y. Besides, it follows from claim 2 that each g_n is greater than 0 (and therefore that ) if n is large enough and that the sequence of all g_n converges to 0. But a sequence of numbers greater than or equal to |y| cannot converge to 0. Since it follows from claim 3 that is irrational and therefore that \pi is irrational. On the other hand, since another consequence of Claim 3 is that, if then \tan x is irrational. Laczkovich's proof is really about the hypergeometric function. In fact, and Gauss found a continued fraction expansion of the hypergeometric function using its functional equation. This allowed Laczkovich to find a new and simpler proof of the fact that the tangent function has the continued fraction expansion that Lambert had discovered. Laczkovich's result can also be expressed in Bessel functions of the first kind J \nu(x). In fact, (where \Gamma is the gamma function). So Laczkovich's result is equivalent to: If x \neq 0, x^2 is rational, and then
This article is derived from Wikipedia and licensed under CC BY-SA 4.0. View the original article.
Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.
Bliptext is not
affiliated with or endorsed by Wikipedia or the
Wikimedia Foundation.