Contents
Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem
In transcendental number theory, the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem is a result that is very useful in establishing the transcendence of numbers. It states the following: In other words, the extension field has transcendence degree n over \mathbb{Q}. An equivalent formulation from, is the following: This equivalence transforms a linear relation over the algebraic numbers into an algebraic relation over \mathbb{Q} by using the fact that a symmetric polynomial whose arguments are all conjugates of one another gives a rational number. The theorem is named for Ferdinand von Lindemann and Karl Weierstrass. Lindemann proved in 1882 that eα is transcendental for every non-zero algebraic number α, thereby establishing that π is transcendental (see below). Weierstrass proved the above more general statement in 1885. The theorem, along with the Gelfond–Schneider theorem, is extended by Baker's theorem, and all of these would be further generalized by Schanuel's conjecture.
Naming convention
The theorem is also known variously as the Hermite–Lindemann theorem and the Hermite–Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem. Charles Hermite first proved the simpler theorem where the αi exponents are required to be rational integers and linear independence is only assured over the rational integers, a result sometimes referred to as Hermite's theorem. Although that appears to be a special case of the above theorem, the general result can be reduced to this simpler case. Lindemann was the first to allow algebraic numbers into Hermite's work in 1882. Shortly afterwards Weierstrass obtained the full result, and further simplifications have been made by several mathematicians, most notably by David Hilbert and Paul Gordan.
Transcendence of
e
and π The transcendence of e and π are direct corollaries of this theorem. Suppose α is a non-zero algebraic number; then {α} is a linearly independent set over the rationals, and therefore by the first formulation of the theorem {eα} is an algebraically independent set; or in other words eα is transcendental. In particular, is transcendental. (A more elementary proof that e is transcendental is outlined in the article on transcendental numbers.) Alternatively, by the second formulation of the theorem, if α is a non-zero algebraic number, then {0, α} is a set of distinct algebraic numbers, and so the set {e0, eα} = {1, eα} is linearly independent over the algebraic numbers and in particular eα cannot be algebraic and so it is transcendental. To prove that π is transcendental, we prove that it is not algebraic. If π were algebraic, πi would be algebraic as well, and then by the Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem (see Euler's identity) would be transcendental, a contradiction. Therefore π is not algebraic, which means that it is transcendental. A slight variant on the same proof will show that if α is a non-zero algebraic number then sin(α), cos(α), tan(α) and their hyperbolic counterparts are also transcendental.
p
-adic conjecture
Modular conjecture
An analogue of the theorem involving the modular function j was conjectured by Daniel Bertrand in 1997, and remains an open problem. Writing for the square of the nome and the conjecture is as follows.
Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem
Proof
The proof relies on two preliminary lemmas. Notice that Lemma B itself is already sufficient to deduce the original statement of Lindemann–Weierstrass theorem.
Preliminary lemmas
Proof of Lemma A. To simplify the notation set: Then the statement becomes Let p be a prime number and define the following polynomials: where ℓ is a non-zero integer such that are all algebraic integers. Define Using integration by parts we arrive at where np-1 is the degree of f_i, and f_i^{(j)} is the j-th derivative of f_i. This also holds for s complex (in this case the integral has to be intended as a contour integral, for example along the straight segment from 0 to s) because is a primitive of. Consider the following sum: In the last line we assumed that the conclusion of the Lemma is false. In order to complete the proof we need to reach a contradiction. We will do so by estimating in two different ways. First is an algebraic integer which is divisible by p! for j\geq p and vanishes for j<p unless j=p-1 and k=i, in which case it equals This is not divisible by p when p is large enough because otherwise, putting (which is a non-zero algebraic integer) and calling the product of its conjugates (which is still non-zero), we would get that p divides, which is false. So J_i is a non-zero algebraic integer divisible by (p − 1)!. Now Since each f_i(x) is obtained by dividing a fixed polynomial with integer coefficients by, it is of the form where g_m is a polynomial (with integer coefficients) independent of i. The same holds for the derivatives. Hence, by the fundamental theorem of symmetric polynomials, is a fixed polynomial with rational coefficients evaluated in \alpha_i (this is seen by grouping the same powers of appearing in the expansion and using the fact that these algebraic numbers are a complete set of conjugates). So the same is true of J_i, i.e. it equals G(\alpha_i), where G is a polynomial with rational coefficients independent of i. Finally is rational (again by the fundamental theorem of symmetric polynomials) and is a non-zero algebraic integer divisible by (p-1)!^n (since the J_i's are algebraic integers divisible by (p-1)!). Therefore However one clearly has: where Fi is the polynomial whose coefficients are the absolute values of those of fi (this follows directly from the definition of I_i(s)). Thus and so by the construction of the f_i's we have for a sufficiently large C independent of p, which contradicts the previous inequality. This proves Lemma A. ∎ Proof of Lemma B: Assuming we will derive a contradiction, thus proving Lemma B. Let us choose a polynomial with integer coefficients which vanishes on all the \gamma(k)'s and let be all its distinct roots. Let b(n + 1) = ... = b(N) = 0. The polynomial vanishes at by assumption. Since the product is symmetric, for any \tau\in S_N the monomials and have the same coefficient in the expansion of P. Thus, expanding accordingly and grouping the terms with the same exponent, we see that the resulting exponents form a complete set of conjugates and, if two terms have conjugate exponents, they are multiplied by the same coefficient. So we are in the situation of Lemma A. To reach a contradiction it suffices to see that at least one of the coefficients is non-zero. This is seen by equipping C with the lexicographic order and by choosing for each factor in the product the term with non-zero coefficient which has maximum exponent according to this ordering: the product of these terms has non-zero coefficient in the expansion and does not get simplified by any other term. This proves Lemma B. ∎
Final step
We turn now to prove the theorem: Let a(1), ..., a(n) be non-zero algebraic numbers, and α(1), ..., α(n) distinct algebraic numbers. Then let us assume that: We will show that this leads to contradiction and thus prove the theorem. The proof is very similar to that of Lemma B, except that this time the choices are made over the a(i)'s: For every i ∈ {1, ..., n}, a(i) is algebraic, so it is a root of an irreducible polynomial with integer coefficients of degree d(i). Let us denote the distinct roots of this polynomial a(i)1, ..., a(i)d(i), with a(i)1 = a(i). Let S be the functions σ which choose one element from each of the sequences (1, ..., d(1)), (1, ..., d(2)), ..., (1, ..., d(n)), so that for every 1 ≤ i ≤ n, σ(i) is an integer between 1 and d(i). We form the polynomial in the variables Since the product is over all the possible choice functions σ, Q is symmetric in for every i. Therefore Q is a polynomial with integer coefficients in elementary symmetric polynomials of the above variables, for every i, and in the variables yi. Each of the latter symmetric polynomials is a rational number when evaluated in. The evaluated polynomial vanishes because one of the choices is just σ(i) = 1 for all i, for which the corresponding factor vanishes according to our assumption above. Thus, the evaluated polynomial is a sum of the form where we already grouped the terms with the same exponent. So in the left-hand side we have distinct values β(1), ..., β(N), each of which is still algebraic (being a sum of algebraic numbers) and coefficients. The sum is nontrivial: if \alpha(i) is maximal in the lexicographic order, the coefficient of is just a product of a(i)j's (with possible repetitions), which is non-zero. By multiplying the equation with an appropriate integer factor, we get an identical equation except that now b(1), ..., b(N) are all integers. Therefore, according to Lemma B, the equality cannot hold, and we are led to a contradiction which completes the proof. ∎ Note that Lemma A is sufficient to prove that e is irrational, since otherwise we may write e = p / q, where both p and q are non-zero integers, but by Lemma A we would have qe − p ≠ 0, which is a contradiction. Lemma A also suffices to prove that π is irrational, since otherwise we may write π = k / n, where both k and n are integers) and then ±iπ are the roots of n2x2 + k2 = 0; thus 2 − 1 − 1 = 2e0 + eiπ + e−iπ ≠ 0; but this is false. Similarly, Lemma B is sufficient to prove that e is transcendental, since Lemma B says that if a0, ..., an are integers not all of which are zero, then Lemma B also suffices to prove that π is transcendental, since otherwise we would have 1 + eiπ ≠ 0.
Equivalence of the two statements
Baker's formulation of the theorem clearly implies the first formulation. Indeed, if are algebraic numbers that are linearly independent over \Q, and is a polynomial with rational coefficients, then we have and since are algebraic numbers which are linearly independent over the rationals, the numbers are algebraic and they are distinct for distinct n-tuples. So from Baker's formulation of the theorem we get for all n-tuples. Now assume that the first formulation of the theorem holds. For n=1 Baker's formulation is trivial, so let us assume that n>1, and let be non-zero algebraic numbers, and distinct algebraic numbers such that: As seen in the previous section, and with the same notation used there, the value of the polynomial at has an expression of the form where we have grouped the exponentials having the same exponent. Here, as proved above, are rational numbers, not all equal to zero, and each exponent \beta(m) is a linear combination of \alpha(i) with integer coefficients. Then, since n>1 and are pairwise distinct, the \Q-vector subspace V of \C generated by is not trivial and we can pick to form a basis for V. For each m=1,\dots,M, we have For each let d_j be the least common multiple of all the d_{m,j} for, and put. Then are algebraic numbers, they form a basis of V, and each \beta(m) is a linear combination of the v_j with integer coefficients. By multiplying the relation by, where N is a large enough positive integer, we get a non-trivial algebraic relation with rational coefficients connecting , against the first formulation of the theorem.
This article is derived from Wikipedia and licensed under CC BY-SA 4.0. View the original article.
Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.
Bliptext is not
affiliated with or endorsed by Wikipedia or the
Wikimedia Foundation.