Contents
Pappus's hexagon theorem
In mathematics, Pappus's hexagon theorem (attributed to Pappus of Alexandria) states that It holds in a projective plane over any field, but fails for projective planes over any noncommutative division ring. Projective planes in which the "theorem" is valid are called pappian planes. If one considers a pappian plane containing a hexagon as just described but with sides Ab and aB parallel and also sides Bc and bC parallel (so that the Pappus line u is the line at infinity), one gets the affine version of Pappus's theorem shown in the second diagram. If the Pappus line u and the lines g,h have a point in common, one gets the so-called little version of Pappus's theorem. The dual of this incidence theorem states that given one set of concurrent lines A, B, C, and another set of concurrent lines a, b, c, then the lines x, y, z defined by pairs of points resulting from pairs of intersections A\cap b and and and b\cap C are concurrent. (Concurrent means that the lines pass through one point.) Pappus's theorem is a special case of Pascal's theorem for a conic—the limiting case when the conic degenerates into 2 straight lines. Pascal's theorem is in turn a special case of the Cayley–Bacharach theorem. The Pappus configuration is the configuration of 9 lines and 9 points that occurs in Pappus's theorem, with each line meeting 3 of the points and each point meeting 3 lines. In general, the Pappus line does not pass through the point of intersection of ABC and abc. This configuration is self dual. Since, in particular, the lines Bc, bC, XY have the properties of the lines x,y,z of the dual theorem, and collinearity of X,Y,Z is equivalent to concurrence of Bc, bC, XY, the dual theorem is therefore just the same as the theorem itself. The Levi graph of the Pappus configuration is the Pappus graph, a bipartite distance-regular graph with 18 vertices and 27 edges.
Proof: affine form
If the affine form of the statement can be proven, then the projective form of Pappus's theorem is proven, as the extension of a pappian plane to a projective plane is unique. Because of the parallelity in an affine plane one has to distinct two cases: and. The key for a simple proof is the possibility for introducing a "suitable" coordinate system: Case 1: The lines g,h intersect at point S=g\cap h. In this case coordinates are introduced, such that (see diagram). B,C have the coordinates. From the parallelity of the lines Bc,; Cb one gets and the parallelity of the lines Ab, Ba yields. Hence line Ca has slope -1 and is parallel line Ac. Case 2: (little theorem). In this case the coordinates are chosen such that. From the parallelity of and one gets and, respectively, and at least the parallelity.
Proof with homogeneous coordinates
Choose homogeneous coordinates with On the lines AC, Ac, AX, given by, take the points B, Y, b to be for some p, q, r. The three lines XB, CY, cb are , so they pass through the same point a if and only if rqp = 1. The condition for the three lines Cb, cB and XY with equations to pass through the same point Z is rpq =1. So this last set of three lines is concurrent if all the other eight sets are because multiplication is commutative, so pq = qp. Equivalently, X, Y, Z are collinear. The proof above also shows that for Pappus's theorem to hold for a projective space over a division ring it is both sufficient and necessary that the division ring is a (commutative) field. German mathematician Gerhard Hessenberg proved that Pappus's theorem implies Desargues's theorem. In general, Pappus's theorem holds for some projective plane if and only if it is a projective plane over a commutative field. The projective planes in which Pappus's theorem does not hold are Desarguesian projective planes over noncommutative division rings, and non-Desarguesian planes. The proof is invalid if C, c, X happen to be collinear. In that case an alternative proof can be provided, for example, using a different projective reference.
Dual theorem
Because of the principle of duality for projective planes the dual theorem of Pappus is true: If 6 lines A,b,C,a,B,c are chosen alternately from two pencils with centers G,H, the lines are concurrent, that means: they have a point U in common. The left diagram shows the projective version, the right one an affine version, where the points G,H are points at infinity. If point U is on the line GH than one gets the "dual little theorem" of Pappus' theorem.
Other statements of the theorem
In addition to the above characterizations of Pappus's theorem and its dual, the following are equivalent statements:
Origins
In its earliest known form, Pappus's Theorem is Propositions 138, 139, 141, and 143 of Book VII of Pappus's Collection. These are Lemmas XII, XIII, XV, and XVII in the part of Book VII consisting of lemmas to the first of the three books of Euclid's Porisms. The lemmas are proved in terms of what today is known as the cross ratio of four collinear points. Three earlier lemmas are used. The first of these, Lemma III, has the diagram below (which uses Pappus's lettering, with G for Γ, D for Δ, J for Θ, and L for Λ). Here three concurrent straight lines, AB, AG, and AD, are crossed by two lines, JB and JE, which concur at J. Also KL is drawn parallel to AZ. Then These proportions might be written today as equations: The last compound ratio (namely JD : GD & BG : JB) is what is known today as the cross ratio of the collinear points J, G, D, and B in that order; it is denoted today by (J, G; D, B). So we have shown that this is independent of the choice of the particular straight line JD that crosses the three straight lines that concur at A. In particular It does not matter on which side of A the straight line JE falls. In particular, the situation may be as in the next diagram, which is the diagram for Lemma X. Just as before, we have (J, G; D, B) = (J, Z; H, E). Pappus does not explicitly prove this; but Lemma X is a converse, namely that if these two cross ratios are the same, and the straight lines BE and DH cross at A, then the points G, A, and Z must be collinear. What we showed originally can be written as (J, ∞; K, L) = (J, G; D, B), with ∞ taking the place of the (nonexistent) intersection of JK and AG. Pappus shows this, in effect, in Lemma XI, whose diagram, however, has different lettering: What Pappus shows is DE.ZH : EZ.HD :: GB : BE, which we may write as The diagram for Lemma XII is: The diagram for Lemma XIII is the same, but BA and DG, extended, meet at N. In any case, considering straight lines through G as cut by the three straight lines through A, (and accepting that equations of cross ratios remain valid after permutation of the entries,) we have by Lemma III or XI Considering straight lines through D as cut by the three straight lines through B, we have Thus (E, H; J, G) = (E, K; D, L), so by Lemma X, the points H, M, and K are collinear. That is, the points of intersection of the pairs of opposite sides of the hexagon ADEGBZ are collinear. Lemmas XV and XVII are that, if the point M is determined as the intersection of HK and BG, then the points A, M, and D are collinear. That is, the points of intersection of the pairs of opposite sides of the hexagon BEKHZG are collinear.
This article is derived from Wikipedia and licensed under CC BY-SA 4.0. View the original article.
Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.
Bliptext is not
affiliated with or endorsed by Wikipedia or the
Wikimedia Foundation.