Contents
Infimum and supremum
In mathematics, the ****infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, and if b is a lower bound of S, then b is less than or equal to the infimum of S. Consequently, the term greatest lower bound (abbreviated as ) is also commonly used. The ****supremum (abbreviated sup; : suprema) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the least element in P that is greater than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the supremum of S exists, it is unique, and if b is an upper bound of S, then the supremum of S is less than or equal to b. Consequently, the supremum is also referred to as the least upper bound (or ). The infimum is, in a precise sense, dual to the concept of a supremum. Infima and suprema of real numbers are common special cases that are important in analysis, and especially in Lebesgue integration. However, the general definitions remain valid in the more abstract setting of order theory where arbitrary partially ordered sets are considered. The concepts of infimum and supremum are close to minimum and maximum, but are more useful in analysis because they better characterize special sets which may have. For instance, the set of positive real numbers \R^+ (not including 0) does not have a minimum, because any given element of \R^+ could simply be divided in half resulting in a smaller number that is still in \R^+. There is, however, exactly one infimum of the positive real numbers relative to the real numbers: 0, which is smaller than all the positive real numbers and greater than any other real number which could be used as a lower bound. An infimum of a set is always and only defined relative to a superset of the set in question. For example, there is no infimum of the positive real numbers inside the positive real numbers (as their own superset), nor any infimum of the positive real numbers inside the complex numbers with positive real part.
Formal definition
A of a subset S of a partially ordered set (P, \leq) is an element y of P such that A lower bound a of S is called an (or, or Join and meet) of S if Similarly, an of a subset S of a partially ordered set (P, \leq) is an element z of P such that An upper bound b of S is called a (or, or Join and meet) of S if
Existence and uniqueness
Infima and suprema do not necessarily exist. Existence of an infimum of a subset S of P can fail if S has no lower bound at all, or if the set of lower bounds does not contain a greatest element. (An example of this is the subset of \mathbb{Q}. It has upper bounds, such as 1.5, but no supremum in \mathbb{Q}.) Consequently, partially ordered sets for which certain infima are known to exist become especially interesting. For instance, a lattice is a partially ordered set in which all subsets have both a supremum and an infimum, and a complete lattice is a partially ordered set in which subsets have both a supremum and an infimum. More information on the various classes of partially ordered sets that arise from such considerations are found in the article on completeness properties. If the supremum of a subset S exists, it is unique. If S contains a greatest element, then that element is the supremum; otherwise, the supremum does not belong to S (or does not exist). Likewise, if the infimum exists, it is unique. If S contains a least element, then that element is the infimum; otherwise, the infimum does not belong to S (or does not exist).
Relation to maximum and minimum elements
The infimum of a subset S of a partially ordered set P, assuming it exists, does not necessarily belong to S. If it does, it is a minimum or least element of S. Similarly, if the supremum of S belongs to S, it is a maximum or greatest element of S. For example, consider the set of negative real numbers (excluding zero). This set has no greatest element, since for every element of the set, there is another, larger, element. For instance, for any negative real number x, there is another negative real number which is greater. On the other hand, every real number greater than or equal to zero is certainly an upper bound on this set. Hence, 0 is the least upper bound of the negative reals, so the supremum is 0. This set has a supremum but no greatest element. However, the definition of maximal and minimal elements is more general. In particular, a set can have many maximal and minimal elements, whereas infima and suprema are unique. Whereas maxima and minima must be members of the subset that is under consideration, the infimum and supremum of a subset need not be members of that subset themselves.
Minimal upper bounds
Finally, a partially ordered set may have many minimal upper bounds without having a least upper bound. Minimal upper bounds are those upper bounds for which there is no strictly smaller element that also is an upper bound. This does not say that each minimal upper bound is smaller than all other upper bounds, it merely is not greater. The distinction between "minimal" and "least" is only possible when the given order is not a total one. In a totally ordered set, like the real numbers, the concepts are the same. As an example, let S be the set of all finite subsets of natural numbers and consider the partially ordered set obtained by taking all sets from S together with the set of integers \Z and the set of positive real numbers \R^+, ordered by subset inclusion as above. Then clearly both \Z and \R^+ are greater than all finite sets of natural numbers. Yet, neither is \R^+ smaller than \Z nor is the converse true: both sets are minimal upper bounds but none is a supremum.
Least-upper-bound property
The is an example of the aforementioned completeness properties which is typical for the set of real numbers. This property is sometimes called. If an ordered set S has the property that every nonempty subset of S having an upper bound also has a least upper bound, then S is said to have the least-upper-bound property. As noted above, the set \R of all real numbers has the least-upper-bound property. Similarly, the set \Z of integers has the least-upper-bound property; if S is a nonempty subset of \Z and there is some number n such that every element s of S is less than or equal to n, then there is a least upper bound u for S, an integer that is an upper bound for S and is less than or equal to every other upper bound for S. A well-ordered set also has the least-upper-bound property, and the empty subset has also a least upper bound: the minimum of the whole set. An example of a set that the least-upper-bound property is \Q, the set of rational numbers. Let S be the set of all rational numbers q such that q^2 < 2. Then S has an upper bound (1000, for example, or 6) but no least upper bound in \Q: If we suppose p \in \Q is the least upper bound, a contradiction is immediately deduced because between any two reals x and y (including \sqrt{2} and p) there exists some rational r, which itself would have to be the least upper bound (if ) or a member of S greater than p (if ). Another example is the hyperreals; there is no least upper bound of the set of positive infinitesimals. There is a corresponding ; an ordered set possesses the greatest-lower-bound property if and only if it also possesses the least-upper-bound property; the least-upper-bound of the set of lower bounds of a set is the greatest-lower-bound, and the greatest-lower-bound of the set of upper bounds of a set is the least-upper-bound of the set. If in a partially ordered set P every bounded subset has a supremum, this applies also, for any set X, in the function space containing all functions from X to P, where f \leq g if and only if for all x \in X. For example, it applies for real functions, and, since these can be considered special cases of functions, for real n-tuples and sequences of real numbers. The least-upper-bound property is an indicator of the suprema.
Infima and suprema of real numbers
In analysis, infima and suprema of subsets S of the real numbers are particularly important. For instance, the negative real numbers do not have a greatest element, and their supremum is 0 (which is not a negative real number). The completeness of the real numbers implies (and is equivalent to) that any bounded nonempty subset S of the real numbers has an infimum and a supremum. If S is not bounded below, one often formally writes If S is empty, one writes
Properties
If A is any set of real numbers then if and only if and otherwise If are sets of real numbers then (unless ) and Identifying infima and suprema If the infimum of A exists (that is, \inf A is a real number) and if p is any real number then p = \inf A if and only if p is a lower bound and for every there is an with Similarly, if \sup A is a real number and if p is any real number then p = \sup A if and only if p is an upper bound and if for every there is an with Relation to limits of sequences If is any non-empty set of real numbers then there always exists a non-decreasing sequence in S such that Similarly, there will exist a (possibly different) non-increasing sequence in S such that Expressing the infimum and supremum as a limit of a such a sequence allows theorems from various branches of mathematics to be applied. Consider for example the well-known fact from topology that if f is a continuous function and is a sequence of points in its domain that converges to a point p, then necessarily converges to f(p). It implies that if is a real number (where all are in S) and if f is a continuous function whose domain contains S and \sup S, then which (for instance) guarantees that f(\sup S) is an adherent point of the set If in addition to what has been assumed, the continuous function f is also an increasing or non-decreasing function, then it is even possible to conclude that This may be applied, for instance, to conclude that whenever g is a real (or complex) valued function with domain whose sup norm is finite, then for every non-negative real number q, since the map defined by f(x) = x^q is a continuous non-decreasing function whose domain [0, \infty) always contains and Although this discussion focused on \sup, similar conclusions can be reached for \inf with appropriate changes (such as requiring that f be non-increasing rather than non-decreasing). Other norms defined in terms of \sup or \inf include the weak L^{p,w} space norms (for ), the norm on Lebesgue space and operator norms. Monotone sequences in S that converge to \sup S (or to \inf S) can also be used to help prove many of the formula given below, since addition and multiplication of real numbers are continuous operations.
Arithmetic operations on sets
The following formulas depend on a notation that conveniently generalizes arithmetic operations on sets. Throughout, are sets of real numbers. Sum of sets The Minkowski sum of two sets A and B of real numbers is the set consisting of all possible arithmetic sums of pairs of numbers, one from each set. The infimum and supremum of the Minkowski sum satisfies and Product of sets The multiplication of two sets A and B of real numbers is defined similarly to their Minkowski sum: If A and B are nonempty sets of positive real numbers then and similarly for suprema Scalar product of a set The product of a real number r and a set B of real numbers is the set If r \geq 0 then while if r \leq 0 then Using r = -1 and the notation it follows that Multiplicative inverse of a set For any set S that does not contain 0, let If is non-empty then where this equation also holds when if the definition is used. This equality may alternatively be written as Moreover, if and only if where if then
Duality
If one denotes by the partially-ordered set P with the opposite order relation; that is, for all declare: then infimum of a subset S in P equals the supremum of S in and vice versa. For subsets of the real numbers, another kind of duality holds: where
Examples
Infima
Suprema
In the last example, the supremum of a set of rationals is irrational, which means that the rationals are incomplete. One basic property of the supremum is for any functionals f and g. The supremum of a subset S of where ,\mid, denotes "divides", is the lowest common multiple of the elements of S. The supremum of a set S containing subsets of some set X is the union of the subsets when considering the partially ordered set, where P is the power set of X and is subset.
This article is derived from Wikipedia and licensed under CC BY-SA 4.0. View the original article.
Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the
Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.
Bliptext is not
affiliated with or endorsed by Wikipedia or the
Wikimedia Foundation.