Cone of curves

1

In mathematics, the cone of curves (sometimes the Kleiman-Mori cone) of an algebraic variety X is a combinatorial invariant of importance to the birational geometry of X.

Definition

Let X be a proper variety. By definition, a (real) 1-cycle on X is a formal linear combination of irreducible, reduced and proper curves C_i, with coefficients. Numerical equivalence of 1-cycles is defined by intersections: two 1-cycles C and C' are numerically equivalent if for every Cartier divisor D on X. Denote the real vector space of 1-cycles modulo numerical equivalence by N_1(X). We define the cone of curves of X to be where the C_i are irreducible, reduced, proper curves on X, and [C_i] their classes in N_1(X). It is not difficult to see that NE(X) is indeed a convex cone in the sense of convex geometry.

Applications

One useful application of the notion of the cone of curves is the Kleiman condition, which says that a (Cartier) divisor D on a complete variety X is ample if and only if for any nonzero element x in, the closure of the cone of curves in the usual real topology. (In general, NE(X) need not be closed, so taking the closure here is important.) A more involved example is the role played by the cone of curves in the theory of minimal models of algebraic varieties. Briefly, the goal of that theory is as follows: given a (mildly singular) projective variety X, find a (mildly singular) variety X' which is birational to X, and whose canonical divisor K_{X'} is nef. The great breakthrough of the early 1980s (due to Mori and others) was to construct (at least morally) the necessary birational map from X to X' as a sequence of steps, each of which can be thought of as contraction of a K_X-negative extremal ray of NE(X). This process encounters difficulties, however, whose resolution necessitates the introduction of the flip.

A structure theorem

The above process of contractions could not proceed without the fundamental result on the structure of the cone of curves known as the Cone Theorem. The first version of this theorem, for smooth varieties, is due to Mori; it was later generalised to a larger class of varieties by Kawamata, Kollár, Reid, Shokurov, and others. Mori's version of the theorem is as follows: Cone Theorem. Let X be a smooth projective variety. Then

  1. There are countably many rational curves C_i on X, satisfying, and
  2. For any positive real number \epsilon and any ample divisor H, where the sum in the last term is finite. The first assertion says that, in the closed half-space of N_1(X) where intersection with K_X is nonnegative, we know nothing, but in the complementary half-space, the cone is spanned by some countable collection of curves which are quite special: they are rational, and their 'degree' is bounded very tightly by the dimension of X. The second assertion then tells us more: it says that, away from the hyperplane, extremal rays of the cone cannot accumulate. When X is a Fano variety, because -K_X is ample. So the cone theorem shows that the cone of curves of a Fano variety is generated by rational curves. If in addition the variety X is defined over a field of characteristic 0, we have the following assertion, sometimes referred to as the Contraction Theorem:
  3. Let be an extremal face of the cone of curves on which K_X is negative. Then there is a unique morphism to a projective variety Z, such that and an irreducible curve C in X is mapped to a point by if and only if [C] \in F. (See also: contraction morphism).

This article is derived from Wikipedia and licensed under CC BY-SA 4.0. View the original article.

Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc.
Bliptext is not affiliated with or endorsed by Wikipedia or the Wikimedia Foundation.

Edit article